Difference between revisions of "Weakly compact"
Zetapology (Talk | contribs) (Many Minor Fixes) |
|||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{DISPLAYTITLE: Weakly compact cardinal}} | {{DISPLAYTITLE: Weakly compact cardinal}} | ||
+ | [[Category:Large cardinal axioms]] | ||
Weakly compact cardinals lie at the focal point of a number | Weakly compact cardinals lie at the focal point of a number | ||
of diverse concepts in infinite combinatorics, admitting various characterizations in terms of these concepts. If $\kappa^{{<}\kappa} = \kappa$, then the following are equivalent: | of diverse concepts in infinite combinatorics, admitting various characterizations in terms of these concepts. If $\kappa^{{<}\kappa} = \kappa$, then the following are equivalent: | ||
− | :; Weak compactness : A cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if and only if it is [[uncountable]] and every $\kappa$-satisfiable theory in an $ | + | :; Weak compactness : A cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if and only if it is [[uncountable]] and every $\kappa$-satisfiable theory in an [[Infinitary logic|$\mathcal{L}_{\kappa,\kappa}$]] language of size at most $\kappa$ is satisfiable. |
:; Extension property : A cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if and only if for every $A\subset V_\kappa$, there is a transitive structure $W$ properly extending $V_\kappa$ and $A^*\subset W$ such that $\langle V_\kappa,{\in},A\rangle\prec\langle W,{\in},A^*\rangle$. | :; Extension property : A cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if and only if for every $A\subset V_\kappa$, there is a transitive structure $W$ properly extending $V_\kappa$ and $A^*\subset W$ such that $\langle V_\kappa,{\in},A\rangle\prec\langle W,{\in},A^*\rangle$. | ||
:; Tree property : A cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if and only if it is [[inaccessible]] and has the [[tree property]]. | :; Tree property : A cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if and only if it is [[inaccessible]] and has the [[tree property]]. | ||
Line 16: | Line 17: | ||
Weakly compact cardinals first arose | Weakly compact cardinals first arose | ||
in connection with (and were named for) the question of | in connection with (and were named for) the question of | ||
− | whether certain infinitary logics satisfy the compactness | + | whether certain [[Infinitary logic|infinitary logics]] satisfy the compactness |
theorem of first order logic. Specifically, in a language | theorem of first order logic. Specifically, in a language | ||
with a signature consisting, as in the first order context, | with a signature consisting, as in the first order context, | ||
of a set of constant, finitary function and relation | of a set of constant, finitary function and relation | ||
− | symbols, we build up the language of $ | + | symbols, we build up the language of $\mathcal{L}_{\kappa,\lambda}$ |
formulas by closing the collection of formulas under | formulas by closing the collection of formulas under | ||
infinitary conjunctions | infinitary conjunctions | ||
Line 33: | Line 34: | ||
satisfiable. First order logic is precisely | satisfiable. First order logic is precisely | ||
$L_{\omega,\omega}$, and the classical Compactness theorem | $L_{\omega,\omega}$, and the classical Compactness theorem | ||
− | asserts that every $\omega$-satisfiable $ | + | asserts that every $\omega$-satisfiable $\mathcal{L}_{\omega,\omega}$ |
theory is satisfiable. A uncountable cardinal $\kappa$ is | theory is satisfiable. A uncountable cardinal $\kappa$ is | ||
''[[strongly compact]]'' if every $\kappa$-satisfiable | ''[[strongly compact]]'' if every $\kappa$-satisfiable | ||
− | $ | + | $\mathcal{L}_{\kappa,\kappa}$ theory is satisfiable. The cardinal |
$\kappa$ is ''weakly compact'' if every | $\kappa$ is ''weakly compact'' if every | ||
− | $\kappa$-satisfiable $ | + | $\kappa$-satisfiable $\mathcal{L}_{\kappa,\kappa}$ theory, in a |
language having at most $\kappa$ many constant, function | language having at most $\kappa$ many constant, function | ||
and relation symbols, is satisfiable. | and relation symbols, is satisfiable. | ||
Line 89: | Line 90: | ||
== Weakly compact cardinals and the constructible universe == | == Weakly compact cardinals and the constructible universe == | ||
− | Every weakly compact cardinal is weakly compact in $L$. | + | Every weakly compact cardinal is weakly compact in [[Constructible universe|$L$]]. <cite>Jech2003:SetTheory</cite> |
Nevertheless, the weak compactness property is not generally downward absolute between transitive models of set theory. | Nevertheless, the weak compactness property is not generally downward absolute between transitive models of set theory. | ||
Line 96: | Line 97: | ||
== Weakly compact cardinals and forcing == | == Weakly compact cardinals and forcing == | ||
− | * Weakly compact cardinals are invariant under small forcing | + | * Weakly compact cardinals are invariant under small forcing. [http://www.math.csi.cuny.edu/~fuchs/IndestructibleWeakCompactness.pdf] |
* Weakly compact cardinals are preserved by the canonical forcing of the GCH, by fast function forcing and many other forcing notions {{Citation needed}}. | * Weakly compact cardinals are preserved by the canonical forcing of the GCH, by fast function forcing and many other forcing notions {{Citation needed}}. | ||
* If $\kappa$ is weakly compact, there is a forcing extension in which $\kappa$ remains weakly compact and $2^\kappa\gt\kappa$ {{Citation needed}}. | * If $\kappa$ is weakly compact, there is a forcing extension in which $\kappa$ remains weakly compact and $2^\kappa\gt\kappa$ {{Citation needed}}. | ||
− | * If the existence of weakly compact cardinals is consistent with ZFC, then there is a model of ZFC in which $\kappa$ is not weakly, but becomes weakly compact in a forcing extension <CITE>Kunen1978:SaturatedIdeals</CITE>. | + | * If the existence of weakly compact cardinals is consistent with ZFC, then there is a model of ZFC in which $\kappa$ is not weakly compact, but becomes weakly compact in a forcing extension <CITE>Kunen1978:SaturatedIdeals</CITE>. |
== Indestructibility of a weakly compact cardinal == | == Indestructibility of a weakly compact cardinal == | ||
Line 106: | Line 107: | ||
== Relations with other large cardinals == | == Relations with other large cardinals == | ||
− | * Every weakly compact cardinal is inaccessible, Mahlo, hyper-Mahlo, hyper-hyper-Mahlo and more. | + | * Every weakly compact cardinal is [[inaccessible]], [[Mahlo]], hyper-Mahlo, hyper-hyper-Mahlo and more. |
− | * Measurable cardinals, Ramsey cardinals, | + | * [[Measurable]] cardinals, [[Ramsey]] cardinals, and [[indescribable|totally indescribable]] cardinals are all weakly compact and a stationary limit of weakly compact cardinals. |
+ | * Assuming the consistency of a [[strongly unfoldable]] cardinal with ZFC, it is also consistent for the least weakly compact cardinal to be the least [[unfoldable]] cardinal. <cite>CodyGitikHamkinsSchanker2013:TheLeastWeaklyCompactCardinal</cite> | ||
+ | *If GCH holds, then the least weakly compact cardinal is not [[weakly measurable]]. However, if there is a [[measurable]] cardinal, then it is consistent for the least weakly compact cardinal to be weakly measurable. <cite>CodyGitikHamkinsSchanker2013:TheLeastWeaklyCompactCardinal</cite> | ||
+ | *If there is a $\kappa$ which is [[nearly supercompact|nearly $\theta$-supercompact]] where $\theta^{<\kappa}=\theta$, then it is consistent for the least weakly compact cardinal to be nearly $\theta$-supercompact. <cite>CodyGitikHamkinsSchanker2013:TheLeastWeaklyCompactCardinal</cite> | ||
{{References}} | {{References}} |
Revision as of 23:13, 10 November 2017
Weakly compact cardinals lie at the focal point of a number of diverse concepts in infinite combinatorics, admitting various characterizations in terms of these concepts. If $\kappa^{{<}\kappa} = \kappa$, then the following are equivalent:
- Weak compactness
- A cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if and only if it is uncountable and every $\kappa$-satisfiable theory in an $\mathcal{L}_{\kappa,\kappa}$ language of size at most $\kappa$ is satisfiable.
- Extension property
- A cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if and only if for every $A\subset V_\kappa$, there is a transitive structure $W$ properly extending $V_\kappa$ and $A^*\subset W$ such that $\langle V_\kappa,{\in},A\rangle\prec\langle W,{\in},A^*\rangle$.
- Tree property
- A cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if and only if it is inaccessible and has the tree property.
- Filter property
- A cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if and only if whenever $M$ is a set containing at most $\kappa$-many subsets of $\kappa$, then there is a $\kappa$-complete nonprincipal filter $F$ measuring every set in $M$.
- Weak embedding property
- A cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if and only if for every $A\subset\kappa$ there is a transitive set $M$ of size $\kappa$ with $\kappa\in M$ and a transitive set $N$ with an embedding $j:M\to N$ with critical point $\kappa$.
- Embedding characterization
- A cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if and only if for every transitive set $M$ of size $\kappa$ with $\kappa\in M$ there is a transitive set $N$ and an embedding $j:M\to N$ with critical point $\kappa$.
- Normal embedding characterization
- A cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if and only if for every $\kappa$-model $M$ there is a $\kappa$-model $N$ and an embedding $j:M\to N$ with critical point $\kappa$, such that $N=\{\ j(f)(\kappa)\mid f\in M\ \}$.
- Hauser embedding characterization
- A cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if and only if for every $\kappa$-model $M$ there is a $\kappa$-model $N$ and an embedding $j:M\to N$ with critical point $\kappa$ such that $j,M\in N$.
- Partition property
- A cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if and only if it enjoys the partition property $\kappa\to(\kappa)^2_2$.
- Indescribability property
- A cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if and only if it is $\Pi_1^1$-indescribable.
Weakly compact cardinals first arose in connection with (and were named for) the question of whether certain infinitary logics satisfy the compactness theorem of first order logic. Specifically, in a language with a signature consisting, as in the first order context, of a set of constant, finitary function and relation symbols, we build up the language of $\mathcal{L}_{\kappa,\lambda}$ formulas by closing the collection of formulas under infinitary conjunctions $\wedge_{\alpha<\delta}\varphi_\alpha$ and disjunctions $\vee_{\alpha<\delta}\varphi_\alpha$ of any size $\delta<\kappa$, as well as infinitary quantification $\exists\vec x$ and $\forall\vec x$ over blocks of variables $\vec x=\langle x_\alpha\mid\alpha<\delta\rangle$ of size less than $\kappa$. A theory in such a language is satisfiable if it has a model under the natural semantics. A theory is $\theta$-satisfiable if every subtheory consisting of fewer than $\theta$ many sentences of it is satisfiable. First order logic is precisely $L_{\omega,\omega}$, and the classical Compactness theorem asserts that every $\omega$-satisfiable $\mathcal{L}_{\omega,\omega}$ theory is satisfiable. A uncountable cardinal $\kappa$ is strongly compact if every $\kappa$-satisfiable $\mathcal{L}_{\kappa,\kappa}$ theory is satisfiable. The cardinal $\kappa$ is weakly compact if every $\kappa$-satisfiable $\mathcal{L}_{\kappa,\kappa}$ theory, in a language having at most $\kappa$ many constant, function and relation symbols, is satisfiable.
Next, for any cardinal $\kappa$, a $\kappa$-tree is a tree of height $\kappa$, all of whose levels have size less than $\kappa$. More specifically, $T$ is a tree if $T$ is a partial order such that the predecessors of any node in $T$ are well ordered. The $\alpha^{\rm th}$ level of a tree $T$, denoted $T_\alpha$, consists of the nodes whose predecessors have order type exactly $\alpha$, and these nodes are also said to have height $\alpha$. The height of the tree $T$ is the first $\alpha$ for which $T$ has no nodes of height $\alpha$. A ""$\kappa$-branch"" through a tree $T$ is a maximal linearly ordered subset of $T$ of order type $\kappa$. Such a branch selects exactly one node from each level, in a linearly ordered manner. The set of $\kappa$-branches is denoted $[T]$. A $\kappa$-tree is an Aronszajn tree if it has no $\kappa$-branches. A cardinal $\kappa$ has the tree property if every $\kappa$-tree has a $\kappa$-branch.
A transitive set $M$ is a $\kappa$-model of set theory if $|M|=\kappa$, $M^{\lt\kappa}\subset M$ and $M$ satisfies $\text{ZFC}^-$, the theory ZFC without the power set axiom (and using collection and separation rather than merely replacement). For any infinite cardinal $\kappa$ we have $H_{\kappa^+}\models\text{ZFC}^-$, and further, if $M\prec H_{\kappa^+}$ and $\kappa\subset M$, then $M$ is transitive. Thus, any $A\in H_{\kappa^+}$ can be placed into such an $M$. If $\kappa^{\lt\kappa}=\kappa$, one can use the downward Löwenheim-Skolem theorem to find such $M$ with $M^{\lt\kappa}\subset M$. So in this case there are abundant $\kappa$-models of set theory (and conversely, if there is a $\kappa$-model of set theory, then $2^{\lt\kappa}=\kappa$).
The partition property $\kappa\to(\lambda)^n_\gamma$ asserts that for every function $F:[\kappa]^n\to\gamma$ there is $H\subset\kappa$ with $|H|=\lambda$ such that $F\upharpoonright[H]^n$ is constant. If one thinks of $F$ as coloring the $n$-tuples, the partition property asserts the existence of a monochromatic set $H$, since all tuples from $H$ get the same color. The partition property $\kappa\to(\kappa)^2_2$ asserts that every partition of $[\kappa]^2$ into two sets admits a set $H\subset\kappa$ of size $\kappa$ such that $[H]^2$ lies on one side of the partition. When defining $F:[\kappa]^n\to\gamma$, we define $F(\alpha_1,\ldots,\alpha_n)$ only when $\alpha_1<\cdots<\alpha_n$.
Contents
Weakly compact cardinals and the constructible universe
Every weakly compact cardinal is weakly compact in $L$. [1]
Nevertheless, the weak compactness property is not generally downward absolute between transitive models of set theory.
Weakly compact cardinals and forcing
- Weakly compact cardinals are invariant under small forcing. [1]
- Weakly compact cardinals are preserved by the canonical forcing of the GCH, by fast function forcing and many other forcing notions [ citation needed ].
- If $\kappa$ is weakly compact, there is a forcing extension in which $\kappa$ remains weakly compact and $2^\kappa\gt\kappa$ [ citation needed ].
- If the existence of weakly compact cardinals is consistent with ZFC, then there is a model of ZFC in which $\kappa$ is not weakly compact, but becomes weakly compact in a forcing extension [2].
Indestructibility of a weakly compact cardinal
To expand using [2]
Relations with other large cardinals
- Every weakly compact cardinal is inaccessible, Mahlo, hyper-Mahlo, hyper-hyper-Mahlo and more.
- Measurable cardinals, Ramsey cardinals, and totally indescribable cardinals are all weakly compact and a stationary limit of weakly compact cardinals.
- Assuming the consistency of a strongly unfoldable cardinal with ZFC, it is also consistent for the least weakly compact cardinal to be the least unfoldable cardinal. [3]
- If GCH holds, then the least weakly compact cardinal is not weakly measurable. However, if there is a measurable cardinal, then it is consistent for the least weakly compact cardinal to be weakly measurable. [3]
- If there is a $\kappa$ which is nearly $\theta$-supercompact where $\theta^{<\kappa}=\theta$, then it is consistent for the least weakly compact cardinal to be nearly $\theta$-supercompact. [3]
References
- Jech, Thomas J. Set Theory. Third, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 2003. (The third millennium edition, revised and expanded) www bibtex
- Kunen, Kenneth. Saturated Ideals. J Symbolic Logic 43(1):65--76, 1978. www bibtex
- Cody, Brent, Gitik, Moti, Hamkins, Joel David, and Schanker, Jason. The Least Weakly Compact Cardinal Can Be Unfoldable, Weakly Measurable and Nearly θ-Supercompact. , 2013. arχiv bibtex